Bob Berwick is planning to write something erudite about
Bayes in a forthcoming post. I cannot do this, for obvious reasons. But I can
throw oil on the fires. The following is my reaction to a paper that Ewan
suggested that I read the critiques of. I doubt that his advice had the
intended consequence. But, as Yogi Berra observed, it’s always hard to accurately
predict how things will turn out, especially in the future. So here goes.
In an effort to calm my disquiet about Bayes and his
contemporary acolytes, Ewan was kind enough to suggest that I read the comments
to this
B&BS (is it just me, or does the acronym suggest something about the
contents?) target article. Of course,
being a supremely complaisant personality, I immediately did as bid, trolling
through the commentaries and even reading the main piece and the response of
the authors to the critics’ remarks so that I could appreciate the subtleties
of the various parries and thrusts.
Before moving forward, I would love to thank Ewan for this tip. The paper is a lark, the comments are
terrific and, all in all, it’s just the kind of heated debate that warms my cold
cynical heart. Let me provide some of my
personal highlights. But, please, read this for yourself. It’s a page-turner,
and though I cannot endorse their views due to my incompetence, I would be lying if I denied being comforted by their misgivings. It’s always
nice to know you are not alone in the intellectual universe (see here).
The main point that the authors Jones and Love (J&L)
make is that, as practiced, there’s not much to current Bayesian analyses,
though they are hopeful that this is repairable (in contrast to many of the
commentators who believe them to be overly sanguine e.g. see Glymour’s comments. BTW, no
fool he!). Indeed, so far as I can tell, they suggest that this is not a
surprise for Bayes as such is little
more than a pretty simple weighted voting scheme to determine which among a set
of given alternatives best fits the
data (see L&J’s 3). There is some
brouhaha over this characterization by the law firm of Chater, Goodman,
Griffiths, Kemp, Oaksford and Tenebaum (they charge well over $1000 per probable
hour I hear), but J&L stick to their guns and characterization (see p. 219)
claiming that the sophisticated procedures that Chater et. al. advert to
“introduces little added complexity” once the mathematical fog is cleared (219).
So, their view is that Bayesianism per se is pretty weak stuff. Let me explain what I take them to
mean. J&L note (section 3 again) that there are two parts to any Bayesian
model, the voting/counting scheme and the structure of the hypothesis space.
The latter provides the alternatives voted on and a weighting of the votes
(some alternatives are given head starts). Now, Bayes’ Rule (BR) is a
specification of how votes should be allocated as data comes in. The hypothesis space is where the real heavy
lifting is done. In effect, in J&L’s view (and they are by no means the
most extreme voices here as the comment sections show) BR, and modern souped up
versions thereof, add very little of explanatory significance to the mix. If so,
J&L observe, then most of the psychological interest of Bayesian models
resides in the structure of the assumed hypotheses spaces, i.e. whatever
interesting results emerge from a Bayesian model, stem not from the counting
scheme but the structure of the hypothesis space. That’s where the empirical meat lies:
All a Bayesian model does is
determine which of the patterns or classes of patterns it is endowed with is
most consistent with the data it is given. Thus, there is no explanation of
where those patterns (i.e. hypotheses) come from. (220)
This is what I meant by saying that, in J&L’s view,
Bayes, in and of itself, amounts to
little more than the view that “people use past experience to decide what to do
or expect in the future” (217). In and of
itself Bayes does not specify or bound the class of possible or plausible
hypothesis spaces and so in and of itself
it fails to make much of a contribution to our understanding of mental life.
Rather, in and of itself, Bayesian
precepts are anodyne: who doesn’t think that experience matters to our mental
life?
This view is, needless to say, heartily contested. Or so it
appears on the surface. So Chater et. al. assert that:
By adopting appropriate representations of a problem
in terms of random variables and probabilistic dependencies between them,
probability theory and its decision theoretic extensions offer a unifying framework
for understanding all aspects of cognition that can be properly understood as
inference under uncertainty: perception, learning, reasoning, language
comprehension and production, social cognition, action planning, and motor
control, as well as innumerable real world tasks that require the integration
of these capacities. (194)
Wow! Seems really opposed to J&L, right? Well maybe not. Note the first seven words of
the quote that I have conveniently highlighted. Take the right representation
of the problem add a dash of BR and out pops all of human psychology. Hmm. Is this antithetical to J&L’s
claims? Not until we factor out how much
of the explanation in these domains comes from the “appropriate
representations” and how much from the probability add on. Nobody (or at least nobody I know) has any
problem adding probabilities to mentalist theories, at least not in principle
(one always wants to see the payoff). However, if we were to ask where the hard
work comes in, J&L argue that it’s in choosing the right hypothesis space
and not in probabilizing up a given such space.
Or this is the way it looks to J&L and many many many, if not most,
of the other commentators.
Let me mote one more thing before ending. J&L also pick
up on something that bothered me in my earlier post. They observe more than a
passing resemblance between modern Bayesians and earlier Behaviorism (see their
section 4). They assert that in many
cases, the hypotheses that populate Bayesian spaces “are not psychological
constructs …but instead reflect characteristics of the environment. The set of
hypotheses, together with their prior probabilities, constitute a description
of the environment by specifying the likelihood of all possible patterns of
empirical observations (e.g. sense data)” (175). J&L go further and claim
that in many cases, modern Bayesians are mainly interested in just covering the
observed behavior, no matter how it is done. Glymour dubs this “Osiander’s
Psychology,” the aim being to “provide a calculus consistent with the
observations” and nothing more. At any
rate, it appears that there is a general perception out there that in practice Bayesians have looked to
“environmental regularities” rather than “accounts of how information is
represented and manipulated in the head” as the correct bases of optimal
inference.
Chater et. al. object to this characterization and allow “mental states over which such [Bayesian] computations exist…” (195). This need not invalidate J&L’s main point however. The problem with Behaviorism was not merely that it eschewed mental states, but that it endorsed a radical form of associationism. Behaviorism is the natural end point of radical associationism for the view postulates that mental structures largely reflect the properties of environmental regularities. If this is correct, then it is not clear what adding mental representations buys you. Why not go directly from regularities in the environment to regularities in behavior and skip the isomorphic middle man.
Chater et. al. object to this characterization and allow “mental states over which such [Bayesian] computations exist…” (195). This need not invalidate J&L’s main point however. The problem with Behaviorism was not merely that it eschewed mental states, but that it endorsed a radical form of associationism. Behaviorism is the natural end point of radical associationism for the view postulates that mental structures largely reflect the properties of environmental regularities. If this is correct, then it is not clear what adding mental representations buys you. Why not go directly from regularities in the environment to regularities in behavior and skip the isomorphic middle man.
It is worth noting that Chater et. al. seem to endorse a
rough vision of this environmentalist project, at least in the domains of vision
and language. As they note “Bayesian approaches to vision essentially involve
careful analysis of the structure of the visual environment” and “in the
context of language acquisition” Bayesians have focused on “how learning
depends on the details of the “linguistic environment,” which determines the
linguistic structures to be acquired” (195).
Not much talk here of structured hypothesis spaces for
vision or language, no mention of Ullman-like Rigidity Principles or principles
of UG. Just a nod towards structured environments and how they drive mental
processing. Nothing prevents Bayesians from including these, but there seems to be a predisposition to focus on environmental influences. Why?
Well, if you believe that the overarching “framework” question is how
data (i.e. environmental input) moves you around a hypothesis space, then maybe
you’ll be more inclined to downplay the role of the structure of that space and
highlight how input (environmental input) moves you around it. Indeed, a
strong environmentalism will be attractive to you if you believe this. Why? Well, given this
assumption then mental structures are just reflections of environmental
regularities and, if so, the name of the psychological game will focus on explaining how data is
processed to identify these regularities.
No need to worry about the structure of hypothesis spaces for they are
simple reflections of environmental regularities, i.e. regularities in the
data.
Of course, this is not a logically
necessary move. Nothing in Bayes requires that one downplay the importance of hypothesis
spaces, but one can see, without too much effort, why these views will live
comfortably together. And it seems that Chater et. al., the leading Young
Bayesians, have no trouble seeing the utility of structured environments to the
Bayesian project. Need I add that this is the source for the expressed unease
in my previous post on Bayes (here).
Let me reitterate one more point and then stop. There is no reason to think that the practice
that J&L describe, even if it is accurate, is endemic to Bayesian modeling.
It is not. Clearly, it is possible to choose hypothesis spaces that are more
psychologically grounded and then investigate the properties of Bayesian models
that incorporate these. However, if the
more critical of the commentators are correct (see Glymour, Rehder, Anderson
a.o.) then the real problem lies with the fact that Bayesians have hyped their
contributions by confusing a useful tool with a theory, and a pretty simple
tool at that. Here are two quotes
expressing this:
Rehder [i.e. in his comment, NH] goes as far as to suggest viewing
the Bayesian framework as a programming language, in which Bayes’ rule is
universal but fairly trivial, and all of the explanatory power lies in the
assumed goals and hypotheses. (218)
…that all viable approaches
ultimately reduce to Bayesian methods does not imply that Byesian inference
encompasses their explanatory contribution. Such an argument is akin to
concluding that, because the dynamics of all macroscopic physical systems can
be modeled using Newton’s calculus, or because all cognitive models can be
programmed in Python, calculus or python constitutes a complete and correct
theory of cognition. (217)
So, in conclusion: go read the paper, the commentaries and
the replies. It’s loads of fun. At the
very least it comforts me to know that there is a large swath of people out
there (some of them prodigiously smart) that have problems not dissimilar to
mine with the old Reverend’s modern day followers. I suspect that were the revolutionary swagger
toned down and replaced with the observation that Bayes provides one possibly useful
way for exploring how to incorporate probabilities into the mental sciences,
nobody would bat an eye. I’m pretty sure
that I wouldn’t. All that we would ask is what one should always ask: what does
doing this buy us?