Let’s say that a Human Language is
a spoken or signed language that human children can naturally acquire. Let a
Tarskian Language be a language for which there is a finitely specifiable
theory of truth. If L is a Human
Language, then for each sentence S of
L, a human child has the capacities
required to understand S. If L is a Tarskian Language, then there is
a (true) theory such that for each sentence S
of L, there is a corresponding
theorem of the following form: True(S)
≡ P; where ‘≡’ is the material
biconditional. Let Kaplanian Languages be those that are fundamentally like
Tarskian Languages, while allowing for some context sensitivity of the sort
illustrated with (1).
(1) I wrote this.
If L is Kaplanian, then for each sentence S of L, there is a corresponding theorem of the following form: for each
assignment A of values to context-sensitive elements of S,
True(S, A) ≡ F(A); where A
might, for example, be such that the thing it assigns to ‘I’ wrote the thing that A
assigns to ‘this’ (or a corresponding deictic
index). We can
also speak of Davidsonian Languages, for which there are truth theories whose
theorems concern certain spatiotemporally located utterances of sentences. But at least for now, let’s not worry about any
differences between Davidsonian and Kaplanian languages.
Here, I want to focus on examples like (2) and their
bearing on thesis (D).
(2) The second numbered example in this
post is false.
(D) for each Human Language L, there is a theory of truth
that can serve as the core of an adequate theory of meaning for L
(D) goes
beyond the conjecture that Human Languages are Davidsonian/Kaplanian.
My
concern is that even if one can (pace
Tarski) specify theories of truth for Human Languages, a theory that consistently
assigns truth conditions to examples like (2) will be too sophisticated to
serve as the core of theory of meaning for a Human Language.
For simplicity, Let ‘Lari’ be a name for the second numbered example in this post
(leaving it open whether examples are sentence-assignment pairs or utterances).
If Lari is truth evaluable, then presumably, Lari is true if and only if the
second numbered example in this post is false. In which case, if Lari is true, then: the second
numbered example in this post is false; and since Lari is that example, Lari is false. But likewise, if Lari is false, then: since Lari is
the second numbered example in this post, Lari is true if and only if Lari is
false; hence, Lari is true. So prima
facie, Lari is neither true nor false. By itself, that’s not paradoxical. Many things
are neither true nor false: dogs, numbers, etc. But if a theory implies that
Lari is true or false, that tells against the theory.
To be sure, there are ways of stipulating consistent truth
theories for languages that generate analogs of (2) and are like English in
other interesting respects. Clever logicians can invent clever theories that
help us avoid certain mistakes in our attempts to describe the world. But it
doesn’t
follow that for each Human Language L,
there is a theory of truth that is not too clever to be the core of a good
theory of meaning for L.
As Davidson noted and Dummett stressed, the idea behind (D)
is that given some
assumptions about how truth is related to the use of expressions—including demonstratives,
indexicals, and nondeclarative sentences—a suitably formulated theory of truth for L can specify what expressions of L
mean by specifying how they determine the conditions in which more complex
sentences of L are true. But such a
theory must meet conditions that may not be jointly satisfiable. First, it has
to be consistent, even given examples like (2). Second, as Foster noted and
Davidson admitted, it seems that the theory will need to have theorems like (3)
without having theorems like (4).
(3) True(‘Ernie snores.’) ≡ Snores(Ernie)
(4) True(‘Ernie snores.’) ≡ Snores(Ernie) &
Precedes(Three, Seven)
Biconditionals like (3) may seem to "specify the
meanings" of object language sentences, now ignoring assignment relativity
for simplicity. But
it is hard to see how a theory that yields
biconditionals like (4) could serve as a theory of meaning for English, especially if theories of meaning are supposed
to be theories of understanding. The
derivability of (3) does not explain why ‘Ernie snores.’ means what it does—much less explain how speakers understand that sentence—if (4) is equally derivable.
Now if you “just” want a theory that specifies truth conditions, it does no
harm if the theory generates boundlessly many instances of (5), so long as [...] is always true.
(5) True(‘Ernie snores.’) ≡ Snores(Ernie) & [...]
And of
course, a theory that generates (3) may not generate (4). It depends on the
axioms and background logic. But a theory that generates (3) and (6) will
generate (7)
(6) True(‘Bert yells.’) ≡ Yells(Bert)
(7) True(‘Ernie snores.’) ≡ Snores(Ernie) & [True(‘Bert yells.’) ≡ Yells(Bert)]
if the
theory permits replacement of ‘P’ with the conjunction of ‘P’ and a theorem. So if you want a theory of
truth to serve as a theory of meaning, you need (i) a very weak background logic
that doesn’t generate
any “overly
intellectual” theorems,
or (ii) a way of identifying the meaning-specifying theorems. I see no
plausible way of providing (ii). And I worry that adopting (i) is at odds with
the logical sophistication—Kripke’s fixed points, Gupta-Belnap revision rules, or whatever—required to describe truth
consistently.
In Knowledge of
Meaning, Larson and Segal do offer an initially attractive version of (i). In
effect, their system for deriving T-theorems only permits replacement of
established equivalents: given P ≡ Q and Q ≡ R, P ≡ R; given x = y, Fx ≡ Fy.
This system, which doesn’t license derivations of T-sentences like (4) or (7), reflects
an interesting hypothesis about the human capacity to apply (lexical and
compositional) semantic competence to particular expressions. But if derivability
is logically blind, apart from replacement of established equivalents, then (8)
will be as derivable as (3) and (6).
(8) True(‘Lari is false.’) ≡ False(Lari)
Of course, (8) can be true if neither ‘Lari is false.’ nor Lari is true or false. Though
if (8) follows from a true theory of meaning, then ‘Lari is false.’ is still truth evaluable. That’s not a contradiction. Perhaps
‘Lari is false.’ is truth evaluable—we know it to be true if and only if Lari is false—by virtue of a certain competence
applying to it. But if this is the best defense of (D), I think that tells
against the strategy of explaining meaning
in terms of speakers knowing theories whose theorems specify how the world needs
to be in order for sentences to be true. Developing this line of thought requires
a second post. Stay tuned: the issues concern linguistic “knowledge” and closure under entailment.
This comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDelete