******
Here is more about the “quality of input” and vocabulary
acquisition matter (see here). Our group has studied this topic (See our
paper published in PNAS, 2013, not connected to the recent Hirsh-Pasek study;
the link for this is here). So I
want to correct the mangled NYTimes article that has generated so much interest
and perhaps will even influence educational policy in future. First, some
facts: Hirsh-Pasek, whose work/speech at
the White House this newspaper article reports, did not specifically look at
possible differences in “quality” (of which, more below) that might vary as a
function of class, wealth, etc. All her
subject learners were of lower class SES, and so could shed no light on whether
or the extent to which “quality input” is unequally distributed across SES
classes, because she had no comparison group (i.e., learners from other than
low SES strata). Yet the implication was left hanging in the NYT air, just by
mentioning that these children were all lower class, that wealthier people
provide classier “communicative foundations” to their offspring. Our own study does in fact make this SES comparison
directly, and the bottom line is that there is no measureable difference in
“quality of input,” if we can define such a thing at all, as a function of
social class. So either ignore what you
read in the NYT, or go read our article and see what you think in the light of
the evidence we presented. There is an
SES-linked difference in the quantity of speech (sheer number of words) infants
hear before the 5th birthday, however.
But now back to what “quality of input” could be, in any
sense relevant to facilitative environments for language learning. The Hirsh-Pasek study isn’t published as yet,
as far as I know, but her “White Paper” summary suggests that she “coded”
maternal speech and behavior for the extent to which it is “symbol infused,” and
related categories that are, perhaps themselves hard to understand or apply
generally. Despite the real
difficulties of such hand coding over highly variable naturalistic
interactions, there are some facts about
nonlinguistic environmental variance in relevant regards that are strong enough
to shine through. Specifically, as our
studies showed, there is a very powerful influence of referential transparency (that’s what “quality” largely comes down
to, when you peel away abstract labels like “foundations of communication” that
appear in this literature). Referential
transparency is simply your good-old commonsensical notion: there are times, during conversational
interaction, when a listener is attentionally focused on a particular thing,
action, etc., and the speaker via gesture, manipulation of the object,
gazing/pointing at it, also mentions it. A blatant case (pace Quine) is saying “This is
a squirrel” while pointing to and gazing at a squirrel in the presence of child’s
close attention to a squirrel. Turns
out that there are stable, measurable, and strikingly large familial differences
in the proportion of time that such informative extralinguistic contexts are
provided to infants (as I said, their presence/frequency unrelated to the
wealth or class of the family), and these differences (already observed in our
sample populations at child age 14 months) predict vocabulary size when
measured 3 years later as these children enter kindergarten. Colin in an earlier blog ably described why
this very large early vocabulary-size difference matters, over the longer run,
in the Real World of school and future job, so I won’t belabor that point. But a few words now on the lexicon and
whether it has any linguistic interest.
Of course it does. As has been evident since the seminal
work of Carol Chomsky on ask/tell/promise/easy/eager, the business of acquiring
the language-specific grammar is inextricably (I hate that word, but it’s right
here) tied up with acquiring the meanings of terms whose interpretation is not so
transparent to referential observation as is, say, “cat.” For instance, imagine a blind child
acquiring “look” and “see.” Or anyone
trying to acquire “think.” This can’t be
done if the input is solely referentially consistent cases, i.e., everyday scenarios
in which thinkers are thinking, but requires in addition (or even instead) access
to predicate-specific licensed syntactic structures. The issues here are not only relevant but
pretty central to linguistic theorizing, in my opinion (see the huge literature
on “syntactic bootstrapping”). But how
about “cat”? After all, learning must
begin with such homely cases, for which referential information provides the
bulk of the basis for identification. They begin to be understood as early as the 6th
month of life. These words provide the
scaffolding for at least rudimentary acquisition of the grammar (mainly: where, structurally speaking, is the
sentential subject in the exposure language) so their acquisition function is
of some preliminary interest for linguistic-developmental theorizing. This first lexical stock forms crucial grounding
information, the first step to enable all the later fancy footwork, i.e., the
gateway to the linguistic-computational achievements that can then – and
therefore – proceed. I hastily remind
that how the concepts themselves (not the words for them) are acquired is an
abiding mystery, but one that necessarily is engaged outside Linguistics,
notably by people who study perceptual development, theory of mind, and the
like (see, e.g., important lines of research from from Spelke; Csibra, and many others).
No comments:
Post a Comment