Every summer I go back to Generative Grammar (GG) re-education
camp. I pick up an old classic (or two) and reread it/them to see what I failed
to understand when I read it/them last and what nuggets there remain to mine.
This year, prompted by a project that I will tell you about soon (in order to
pick your collective brains) I re-read Syntactic
Structures (SS), Topics (T) and Language and Mind (L&M) (well, I’m
in the middle of the last two and have read the first twice). At any rate,
several things struck me and they seemed like good blog fodder, so let me
share.
Before I got into linguistics (when I was still but a starry
eyed philo major (no cracks please, too easy)) I though that deep structure
was, well, deep. After all why call it deep
structure if it was just another level, without particular significance. Wasn’t
it, after all, the place where Gs met semantics (at least in both SS and the
standard theory) and wasn’t meaning deep?
Moreover, I was not the only one who thought this. The
popular press circulating around GG always seemed to zero in on “deep
structure,” surface structure being so, well, surfacy. Like any philosopher,
given a choice between plumbing the depths and skimming the surface I was all
for going down and deep.
As I grew more sophisticated I came to realize the error of
my ways and how terminology had mislead me. I would sneer at terminologically
naived neophytes who failed to appreciate that “deep” did not mean
“fundamental.” I would knowingly intone that deep structure was just another
level and of no more intrinsic significance that any other level. I would also
glibly point out that meaning was not restricted to deep structure as the
Katz-Postal hypothesis was slowly giving way to interpretive theories of
semantic interpretation where surface structure fed some aspects of meaning
(Jackendoff 1972 being the seminal text).[1]
And I was wrong. Sophistication be damned, deep structure
really was/is deep, even if not in the way that I originally thought. That’s
what my summer rereading of the big three above showed me. So, why is deep
structure deep in the sense of terrifically significant to the GG enterprise?
Here’s why in one phrase: linguistic creativity (LC).
Chomsky noted that the fact of LC was underappreciated.
Humans are able to appropriately produce and easily understand a (practically)
infinite number of linguistic expressions. Or, as a matter of course, humans
produce or parse linguistic expressions they have never before encountered. The
capacity to do this requires that they
have internalized a system of rules. What kinds? Rules that tightly couple a
linguistic expression’s meaning with that linguistic expression’s articulation
(sound, gesture). Absent this kind of theory (aka a grammar that generates an
infinite number of sound meaning pairings) there is no possible account for
this easily observed fact that humans are linguistically creative.
Moreover, as Chomsky argues in SS and L&M and T, the
structure required to code for articulations are insufficient to represent core
aspects of meaning. Here’s Chomsky in Topics
(17):
It is clear…that deep structures
must be quite different from this surface structure. For one thing, the surface
representation in no way expresses the grammatical relations that are…crucial
for semantic interpretation. Secondly, in the case of ambiguous sentences such
as, for example, (5), only a single surface structure may be assigned but the
deep structures must obviously differ. Such examples …are sufficient to
indicate…that deep structures cannot be identified with surface structures. The
inability of surface structures to indicate semantically significant
grammatical relations (i.e., to serve as deep structures) is one fundamental
fact that motivated the development of transformational generative grammar…
Thus any account of LC which wants to account for the human
capacity to use an unbounded number of linguistic expressions (i.e. linguistic
expressions a given native speaker has never before encountered) must include a
system of rules that recursively generate sound meaning pairings based on
different kinds of representations that are G related. Given LC and the fact meaning
structures are different from sound structures there really is no other logical option than something like a
transformational GG.
Before proceeding, I want to make an unpaid political
announcement. GG has been regularly accused of dissing meaning. For example, the
autonomy of syntax is often misunderstood as the irrelevance of semantics. As
you all know, this is completely bogus. The autonomy of syntax thesis is the very
very weak claim. It notes that syntactic properties are not reducible to
semantic (or phonetic) ones. It does not deny that meaning (and sound) facts
are G irrelevant.
Moreover, Chomsky emphasizes this point in all three works.
In both T and L&M he emphasizes that the BIG problem with earlier
Structuralism was its inability to accommodate the simplest facts about meaning
(in particular what we now call theta roles (who did what to whom)). Thus, how
language delivers meaning was at the center of Chomsky’s novel GG proposals and
was the central feature of his critique of Structuralism. And this is not
something that it takes sophisticated close textual analysis to discover. This
leads me to think that many (maybe most) critics of GG’s syntactocentrism
simply did not (and have not) read the work being criticized. Not only is this
deeply ignorant, but is is intellectually irresponsible as well. Sadly, this
kind of ignorant criticism has become a hallmark of the anti GG literature,
something that people like Evans (see here
and links provided) and Everett (see here)
among others have further personalized. However, what is clear on rereading
these classics is that these critiques are not based on even a cursory reading
of the relevant texts.
Ok, back to the main programming: So, LC properly described leads
quickly to the modern conception of grammar, one with distinctive levels for
the coding of articulatory and semantic information (surface structure (S-S)
and deep structure (D-S)) and
operations that unite these levels (aka, transformations (T)). So what made
deep structure deep was the realization that LC required it and once one had
D-S and understood it to be structurally distinct from S-S then one needed Ts
to relate them and the whole modern GG enterprise is up and running. Here’s
Chomsky in L&M (17):
…the speaker makes infinite use of
finite means. His grammar must, then, contain a finite system of rules that
generate infinitely many deep and surface structures, appropriately related. It
must also contain rules that related these abstract structures to certain
representations of sound and meaning…
Well actually, most
(not all) of the modern GG enterprise is motivated by the fact of LC, in
particular the project of specifying the properties of particular human Gs and
the enterprise of specifying the properties humans must have for acquiring
these Gs. The minimalist program adds an extra dimension: the extra question
(already mooted in these early works btw) of separating out the linguistically
specific factors underlying these two capacities from the more cognitively and
computationally general ones that are underlie capacities but are not
specifically linguistically dedicated.
So, a recursive G is part of any theory aspiring to address
the fact of LC and given the difference between S-S and D-S this G will have at
least a D-S level, an S-S level and a T component to relate them. And this
brings us to why deep structure was a deep discovery. Critically, structuralism
was ready to recognize something like S-S. What structuralism missed was any
level analogous to D-S, the level relevant to semantic interpretation. Again
Chomsky in L&M (19):
…[M]odern structural and
descriptive linguistics … restricts itself to the analysis of what I have
called surface structure, to formal properties that are explicit in the signal
and to phrases and units that can be determined from the signal by techniques
of segmentation and classification…[S]uch taxonomic analysis leaves no place
for the deep structures…[which] cannot be derived…by segmentation and
classification of segmented units, nor can the transformational operations
relating deep and surface structure…
So, what brought down classical structuralism and the
Empiricist/Behaviorist psychology that it embraced? Well, the observation that
LC required something like D-S. That, in short, is one reason why D-S really is
deep.
I should add that the relevance of this line of thinking to
G issues has still not been entirely internalized. There is an industry trying
to show that phrase structure can be statistically induced from the signal,
thinking that were this so the GG enterprise would be fatally wounded (see
Elissa Newport’s work on this for example). There is nary a mention of the
problem of relating D-Sish facts and S-Sish facts. The idea seems to be that if
we could just get hierarchically structured S-Ss from the signal the whole GG
project as envisioned by Chomsky over 60 years ago would be discredited as
fundamentally empirically flawed. There is little recognition that the problems
for structuralism and its attendant empiricist psychology started from the
concession that S-S might be amenable
to standard analytic (associationist) techniques.[2]
The problem was that structuralism left out half the problem, the D-S part.
Things, sadly, are no better today in much of the anti-GG literature.
There is a second reason that D-S was considered deep: it
pointed to where language was likely to be invariant. Chomsky notes this in
L&M discussing the philosophical grammarians (e.g. Port Royal types). He
observes that modern conceptions of GG “make the assumption that languages will
differ very little despite considerable diversity in superficial realization”
(76). Where will languages be “similar”? “[O]nly at the deeper level , the
level at which grammatical relations are expressed and at which the processes
that provide for the creative aspect of language use are to be found” (77).
Thus, D-S and the attendant operations that deliver a corresponding S-S were
the natural locus of invariance given the
obvious surface diversity of natural languages. Thus, the other deep
property of D-S was that it and the principles mapping it to S-S were likely to
be invariant across Gs, these invariances being key features of UG.
So, deep structure had some important features that arguably
made it deep. But I can sense all you minimalists out there developing an
uncomfortable intellectual itch that can be characterized roughly as follows:
how deep could deep structure be given that contemporary theories have
dispensed with it. Good itch. Let me scratch.
First, we have retained much of the point of deep structure
in contemporary theory. So, for example, nobody now thinks that the syntactic
structure relevant to surface phonetic form is the same as required to code for
underlying grammatical function/thematic form. Indeed, given the predicate
internal subject hypothesis there is almost no sentence, no matter how simple
in which the underlying semantic subject (the external argument) starts in
surface subject position (e.g. Spec T). The structure relevant to phon
interpretation is understood as different from the syntax relevant for sem
interpretation and it is taken for granted that any adequate G will have to
generate an infinite number of phon-sem pairs. In other words, the moral of D-S has been completely
internalized.
So too has the idea that D-S is G invariant. Contemporary
syntactic theory does not tolerate variation in the mapping of theta roles to
initial phrase marker positions. We are all UTAHers now! Thus, we do not expect
Gs just like English but where affected objects are underlying subjects and
agents are underlying objects. This is not a dimension of permissible
variation. Nor do we expect the mapping principles that deliver CI (and
possibly AP) interpretable objects to differ significantly. Operations are
constrained by universal principles like phase impenetrability (aka
subjacency), the ECP, minimality, etc. When we think of universals in GG, this
is the kind of thing we are assuming.
GG makes no claim about surface invariances. We expect the overt surface
properties of language to vary dramatically. We expect little CI/LF variation
and no variation in the principles of UG. Thus, invariance lives in the forms/derivations
that feed CI, not in the surface realizations of these derivations. Again, this
endorses much of the D-S conceptions outlined in SS, L&M and Topics.
So where the difference? Modern syntactic theory,
minimalism, has largely abandoned the technology of D-S, not its grammatical
point. Minimalism no longer assumes that there is a G level like deep structure
or D-structure, i.e. a level at which
GFs are determined by something like a phrase structure rules. This was part of
every prior (Chomskyan) GG theory. The rejection of D-S (and its analogues) has
been more or less complete.
We have given up the idea that D-S is the product of PS
rules which all apply prior to displacement operations. In fact, thoroughly
modern Minimalists don’t recognize a formal distinction between E-merge and I-merge,
both just being instances of the same underlying Merge operation. Furthermore,
Bare Phrase Structure has eliminated the distinction between Structure building
and lexical insertion so critical to earlier D-S conceptions. In modern theory there
is strictly speaking nothing like a PS rule anymore and so not much left of the
idea that the Grammatical Functions relevant to semantic interpretation are
coded via PS rules.
There remains one last residue of the old technical D-S
idea. Some (e.g. Chomsky and PRO lovers everywhere) still hold onto the view
that the logical GF roles are products of E-merge exclusively. Others (e.g.
moi) do not restrict GF marking to E-merge, but allow that marking via I-merge.
However, this is really the last place where the technical notion of D-S has
life. I, of course, believe that I am right and Chomsky is wrong here (though I
would not bet on myself, at least not a lot). However, this is really the last
residue of the older conception of D-S as a level. The technical conception seems largely gone, though the empirical and
conceptual points D-S served have been completely internalized.
Last point: here’s something else that struck me in
rereading this literature: why is it that S-S and D-S don’t perfectly match.
One can imagine a world in which these two had to coincide. In such a world
there would be two articulations of flying
planes can be dangerous (one corresponding to each interpretation) and
passives (where surface and underlying grammatical relations do not coincide)
would not exist. This is a perfectly conceivable universe, but it is not ours.
Why not? Why is D-S distinct from S-S? Why don’t they match one to one? Might
the mere fact that these two kinds of information are differentially encoded
support Chomsky’s recent suggestions that the mapping to articulation is a late
accretion and that the primary mapping is from something like D-S to SI? I
don’t know, but it is curious that our world is not more neatly arranged. And
that it is not, should be something we think about, and maybe one day address.
That’s it for now. The discovery of D-S launched the modern
GG enterprise. The existence of D-Sish facts and what they means for GG are now
part of the common wisdom. It is fair to say that D-S focused scientific
attention on LC and Plato’s problem. If that ain’t “deep” I don’t know what
could be.
[1]
A great book btw, one that I would still recommend highly.
[2]
Btw, this is almost certainly false once one starts thinking about how to
“abstract” out categories that allow for recursion. It is one thing to define
the VP in John saw the dog via these
simple techniques and another to define the VPs in John saw the dog that Bill thinks that Mary kissed using them. Once
we consider categories with recursive subparts the standard analytic techniques
quickly fail. Simple phrase structure might be statistically coaxed from
surface forms. Interesting ones with complex structure will not be.
No comments:
Post a Comment