I am in the process of co-editing a volume on Syntactic Structures (SS) that is due
out in 2017 to celebrate (aka, exploit) the 60th anniversary of the
publication of this seminal work. I am part of a gang of four (the other culprits
being Howard Lasnik, Pritti Patel, Charles Yang supervised/inspired by Norbert
Corver). We have solicited about 15 shortish pieces on various themes. The
tentative title is something like The
continuing relevance of Syntactic Structures to GG. Look for it on your
newsstands sometime late next year. It should arrive just in time for the 2017
holidays and is sure to be a great Xmas/ Hanukka/Kwanza gift. As preparation
for this editorial escapade, I have re-read SS several times and have tried to
figure out for myself what its lasting contribution is. Clearly it is an
important historical piece as it
sparked the Generative Enterprise. The question remains: What SS ideas have current relevance? Let me mention five.
The first and most important idea centers on the aims of
linguistic theory (ch 6). SS contrasts the study of grammatical form and the particular internal
(empirically to be determined) “simplicity” principles that inform it with
discovery procedures that are “practical and mechanical” (56) methods that “an investigator (my emph, NH) might
actually use, if he had the time, to construct a grammar of the language
directly from the raw data” (52). SS argues that a commitment to discovery
procedures leads to strictures on grammatical
analysis (e.g. bans on level mixing) that are methodologically and
empirically dubious.
The discussion in SS is reminiscent of the well-known
distinction in the philo of science between the context of discovery and the
context of justification. How one finds one’s theory can be idiosyncratic and
serendipidous, justifying one’s “choice” is another matter entirely. SS makes
the same point.[1]
It proposes a methodology of research in which grammatical argumentation is
more or less the standard of resaoning in the sciences more generally: data plus
general considerations of simplicity are deployed to argue for the superiority
of one analysis over another. SS contrasts this with the far stronger strictures
Structuralists endorsed, principles which if seriously practiced would sink
most any serious science. In practice then, what SS is calling for is that
linguists act like regular scientists (in modern parlance, reject
methodological dualism).
Let me be bit more specific. The structuralism that SS was
arguing against took as a methodological dictum that the aim of analysis was to
classify a corpus into a hierarchy of categories conditioned by substitution
criteria. So understood, grammatical categories are classes of words, which are
definable as classes of morphemes, which are defniable as classes of phonemes,
which are definable as classes of phones. The higher levels are, in effect,
simple generalizations over lower
level entities. The thought was that higher level categories were entirely
reducible to lower level distributional patterns. In this sort of analysis,
there are no (and can be no) theoretical entities, in the sense of real
abstract constructs that have empirical consequences but are not reducible or
definable in purely observational terms. By arguing against discovery
procedures and in favor of evaluation metrics SS is in effect arguing for the
legitimacy of theoretical
linguistics. Or, more accurately, for the legitimacy of normal scientific inquiry into language without methodological
constrictions that would cripple physics were it applied.
Let me put this another way: Structuralism adopted a strong
Empiricist methodology in which theory was effectively a summary of
observables. SS argues for the Rationalist conception of inquiry in which
theory must make contact with observables, but is not (and cannot) be reduced
to them. Given that the Rationalist
stance simply reflects common scientific practice, SS is a call for linguists to
start treating language scientifically and not hamstring inquiry by adopting
unrealistic, indeed non-scientific, dicta. This is why SS (and GG) is
reasonably seen as the start of the modern science
of linguistics.
Note that the discussion here in SS differs substantially
from that in chapter 1 of Aspects,
though there are important points of contact.[2]
SS is Rationalist as concerns the research methodology of linguists. Aspects is Rationalist as concerns the
structure of human mind/brains. The former concerns research methodology. The
latter concerns substantive claims about human neuro-psychology.
That said there are obvious points of contact. For example,
if discovery procedures fail methodologically, then this strongly suggests that
they will also fail as theories of linguistic mental structures. Syntax, for
example, is not reducible to
properties of sound and/or meaning despite its having observable consequences
for both. In other words, the Autonomy of Syntax thesis is just a step away
from the rejection of discovery procedures. It amounts to the claim that syntax
constitutes a viable G level that is not reducible to the primitives and
operations of any other G level.
To beat this horse good and dead: Gs contain distinct levels
that interact with empirically evaluable consequences, but they are not
organized so that lower levels are definable in terms of generalizations over
lower level entities. Syntax is real. Phonology is real. Semantics is real.
Phonetics is real. These levels have their own primitives and principles of
operation. The levels interact, but are ontologically autonomous. Given the
modern obsession with deep learning and its implicit endorsement of discovery
procedures, this point is worth reiterating and keeping in mind. The idea that
Gs are just generalizations over generalizations over generalizations that
seems the working hypothesis of Deep Learners and others[3]
has a wide following nowadays so it is worth recalling the SS lesson that
discovery procedures both don’t work and are fundamentally anti-theoretical. It
is Empiricism run statistically amok!
Let me add one more point and then move on. How should we
understand the SS discussion of discovery procedures from an Aspects perspective given that they are
not making the same point? Put more pointedly, don’t we want to understand how
a LAD (aka, kid) goes from PLD (a corpus) to a G? Isn’t this the aim of GG
research? And wouldn’t such a function be
a discovery procedure?
Here’s what I think: Yes and no. What I mean is that SS makes
a distinction that is important to still keep in mind. Principles of FL/UG are
not themselves sufficient to explain how LADs acquire Gs. More is required. Here’s
a quote from SS (56):
Our ultimate aim is to provide an
objective, non-intuitive way to evaluate a grammar once presented, and to
compare it with other proposed grammars (equivalently, the nature of linguistic
structure) and investigating the empirical consequences of adopting a certain
model for linguistic structure, rather than showing how, in principle, one
might have arrived at the grammar of a language.
Put in slightly more modern terms: finding FL/UG does not by
itself provide a theory of how the LAD actually acquires a G. More is needed.
Among other things, we need accounts of how we find phonemes, and morphemes and
many of the other units of analysis the levels require. The full theory will be
very complex, with lots of interacting parts. Many mental modules will no doubt
be involved. Understanding that there is a peculiarly linguistic component to this story does not imply forgetting that
it is not the whole story. SS makes this very clear. However, focusing on the
larger problem often leads to ignoring the fundamental linguistic aspects of
the problem, what SS calls the internal conditions on adequacy, many/some of
which will be linguistically proprietary.[4]
So, the most important contribution of SS is that it
launched the modern science of linguistics by arguing against discovery
procedures (i.e. methodological dualism). And sadly, the ground that SS should
have cleared is once again infested. Hence, the continuing relevance ot the SS
message.
Here are four more ideas of continuing relevance.
First, SS shows that speaker intuitions are a legitimate
source of linguistic data. The discussions of G adequacy in the first several
chapters are all framed in terms of what speakers know about sentences. Indeed,
that Gs are models of human linguistic behavior over an unbounded domain is quite explicit (15):
…a grammar mirrors the
behavior of speakers who, on the basis of a finite and accidental experience
with language, can produce or understand an indefinite number of new sentences.
Indeed, any explication of “grammatical in L” …can be thought of as offering an
explanation for this fundamental aspect of linguistic behavior.
Most of the data presented for choosing one form of G over
another involves plumbing a native speaker’s sense of what is and isn’t natural
for his/her language. SS has an elaborate discussion of this in chapter 8 where
the virtues of “constructional homonymity” (86) as probes of grammatical
adequacy are elaborated. Natural languages are replete with sentences that have
the same phonological form but differ thematically (flying planes can be dangerous) or that have different phonological
forms but are thematically quite similar (John
hugged Mary, Mary was hugged by John).
As SS notes (83): “It is reasonable to expect grammars to provide explanations
for some of these facts” and for theories of grammar to be evaluated in terms
of their ability to handle them.
It is worth noting that the relevance of constructional
homonymity to “debates” about structure dependence has been recently
highlighted once again in a paper by Berwick, Pietroski, Yankama and Chomsky (see here
and here
for discussion). It appears that too many forget that linguistics facts go
beyond the observation that “such and such a strong…is or is not a sentence”
(85). SS warns against forgetting this, and the world would be a better place
(or at least dumb critiques of GG would be less thick on the ground) if this
warning 60 years ago had been heeded.
Second, SS identifies the central problem of linguistics as
how to relate sound and meaning (the latter being more specifically thematic
roles (though this term is not used)). This places Gs and their structure at
the center of the enterprise. Indeed, this is what makes constructional
homonymity such an interesting probe into the structure of Gs. There is an
unbounded number of these pairings and the rules that pair them (i.e. Gs) are
not “visible.” This means the central problem in linguistics is determining the
structure of these abstract Gs by examining their products. Most of SS exhibits
how to do this and the central arguments in favor of adding transformations to
the inventory of syntactic operations involve noting how transformational
grammars accommodate such data in simple and natural ways.
This brings us to the third lasting contribution of SS. It
makes a particular proposal concerning the kind
of G natural languages embody. The right G involves Transformations (T). Finite
State Gs don’t cut it, nor can simple context free PSGs. T-grammars are
required. The argument against PSGs
is particularly important. It is not that they cannot generate the right
structures but that they cannot do so in
the right way, capturing the evident generalizations that Gs embodying Ts
can do.
Isolating Ts as grammatically central operations sets the
stage for the next 50 years of inquiry: specifying the kinds of Ts required and
figuring out how to limit them so that they don’t wildly overgenerate.
SS also proposes the model that until very recently was at
the core of every GG account. Gs contained a PSG component that generated
kernel sentences (which effectively specified thematic dependencies) and a T
component that created further structures from these inputs. Minimalism has
partially stuck to this conception. Though it has (or some versions have)
collapsed PSG kinds of rules and T rules treating both as instances of Merge,
minimalist theories have largely retained the distinction between operations
that build thematic structure and those that do everything else. So, even
though Ts and PSG rules are formally the same, thematic information (roughly
the info carried by kernel sentences in SS) is the province of E-merge
applications and everything else the province of I-merge applications. The
divide between thematic information and all other kinds of semantic information
(aka the duality of interpretation) has thus been preserved in most modern accounts.[5]
Last, SS identifies two different linguistic problems:
finding a G for a particular L and finding a theory of Gs for arbitrary L. This
can also be seen as explicating the notions “grammatical in L” for a given
language L vs the notion of “grammatical” tout court. This important
distinction survives to the present as the difference between Gs and FL/UG. SS
makes it clear (at least to me) that the study of the notion grammatical in L is interesting to the
degree that it serves to illuminate the more general notion grammatical for arbitrary L (i.e. Gs are
interesting to the degree that they illuminate the structure of FL/UG). As a practical
matter, the best route into the more general notion proceeds (at least
initially) via the study of the properties of individual Gs. However, SS warns
against thinking that a proper study of the more general notion must await the
development of fully adequate accounts of the more specific.
Indeed, I would go further. The idea that investigations of
the more general notion (e.g. of FL/UG) are parasitic on (and secondary to)
establishing solid language particular Gs is to treat the more general notion
(UG) as the summary (or generalization of) of properties of individual Gs. In
other words, it is to treat UG as if it were a kind of Structuralist level,
reducible to the properties of individual Gs. But if one rejects this
conception, as the SS discussion of levels and discovery procedures suggests we
should, then prioritizing G facts and investigation over UG considerations is a
bad way to go.
I suspect that the above conclusion is widely appreciated in
the GG community with only those committed to a Greenbergian conception of
Universals dissenting. However, the logic carries over to modern minimalist
investigation as well. The animus against minimalist theorizing can, IMO, be
understood as reflecting the view that such airy speculation must play second
fiddle to real linguistic (i.e. G
based) investigations. SS reminds us that the hard problem is the abstract one
and that this is the prize we need to focus on, and that it will not just solve itself if we just do concentrate on
the “lower” level issues. This would hold true of the world was fundamentally Structuralist,
with higher levels of analysis just being generalizations of lower levels. But
SS argues repeatedly that this is not
right. It is a message that we should continue to rehearse.
Ok, that’s it for now. SS is chock full of other great bits
and the collection we are editing will, I am confident, bring them out. Till
then, let me urge you to (re)read SS and report back on your favorite parts. It is excellent holiday
reading, especially if read responsively accompanied by some good wine.
[2]
Indeed, the view in Aspects is
clearly prefigured in SS, though is not as highlighted in SS as it is later on
(see discussion p. 15).
…a grammar mirrors the behavior
of speakers who, on the basis of a finite and accidental experience with
language, can produce or understand an indefinite number of new sentences.
Indeed, any explication of “grammatical in L” …can be thought of as offering an
explanation for this fundamental aspect of linguistic behavior.
[3]
Elissa Newport’s work seems to be in much the same vein in treating everything
as probability distributions over lower level entities bottoming out in
something like syllables or phones.
[4]
Of course, the ever hopeful minimalist will hope that not very much will be
such.
[5]
I would be remiss if I did not point out that this is precisely the assumption
that the movement theory of control rejects.
A great summary of the highlights! I think the autonomy/indepenence thesis perhaps deserves a mention in its own right. I've lost count of how many times I've heard/read that Chomsky rejects semantics as a discipline. It is clear in SS, and subsequent work, that the claim is not only that syntax is not reducible to semantics, but that progress can be made on semantic issues precisely by gaining a better understanding of syntax as a constraint upon meaning. Of course, there have been many twists and turns since '57, but the basic insight that semantics can be pursued as an interface problem rather than as a problem of communication or reference seems as pertinent today as it was revolutionary back then.
ReplyDeleteyep. Also beautifully brought out in that opening essay in `essays on form and interpretation'.
DeleteIndeed! It's about time that book was reissued. I spent a lot of money for a battered copy:)
DeleteMy favorite - and the reason I think it can and should kick off almost any linguistics course at all - is that not only is there a concrete proposal about the family of Gs, but we are shown that one can PROVE things about the family of Gs - and not only that, you can develop mathematical proofs about what the possible Gs must be using nothing more than the extension of a particular G (the "string language"), and (though not shown) those proofs can be pretty airtight and (though not shown) the same results then apply to *any* further grammatical formalism, regardless of the intension of the Gs. Underappreciated and maligned by many linguists still after the distance that developed between linguistics and the formal language community (under the belief that this method presupposes a claim that matching the string language was *sufficient* for a linguistic theory - which it obviously does not). Hope this point sees a solid treatment in the book.
ReplyDelete