There is currently a fight going on in cog-neuro whose
outcome GGers should care about. It is illuminatingly discussed in a recent
paper by Krakauer, Ghazanfar, Gomez-Marin, MacIver and Poeppel (KGG-MMP) (here).
The fight is about how to investigate the mind/brain connection. There are two
positions. One, which I will call the “Wrong View” (WV) just to have a useful
mnemonic, takes a thoroughly reductionist approach to the problem. The idea is
that a full understanding of brain function will follow from a detailed
understanding of “their component parts and molecular machinery” (480). The
contrary view, which I dub the “Right View” (RV) (again, just to have a name),[1]
thinks that reductionism will not get nearly as far as we need to go and that
the only way to get a full understanding of how brains contribute to
thinking/feeling/etc. requires neural implementations in tandem with (and more
likely subsequent to) “careful theoretical and experimental decomposition of
behavior.” More specifically, “the detailed analysis of tasks and of the
behavior they elicit is best suited for discovering component processes and
their underlying algorithms. In most cases,…the study of the neural
implementation of behavior is best investigated after such behavioral work” (480). In other words, WV and RV differ
not over the end game (an understanding of how the brain subvenes the brain
mechanisms relevant to behavior) but the best route to that end. WV thinks that
if you take care of the neuronal pennies, the cognitive dollars will take care
of themselves. The RV thinks that doing so will inevitably miss the cognitive forest
for the neural trees and might in fact even obscure the function of the neural
trees in the cognitive forest. (God I love to mix metaphors!!). Of course, RV
is right and WV is wrong. I would like to review some of the points KGG-MMP
makes arguing this. However, take a look for yourself. The paper is very
accessible and worth thinking about more carefully.
Here are some points that I found illuminating (along with
some points of picky disagreement (or, how I would have put things differently)).
First, framing the issue as one of “reductionism” confuses
matters. The issue is less reduction than it is a neurocentric myopia. The
problem KGG-MMP identifies revolves around the narrow methods standard practice
deploys not the ultimate metaphysics that it endorses. In other words, even if
there is, ontologically speaking, nothing more than “neurons” and their
interactions,[2]
discovering what these interactions are and how they combine to yield the
observed mental life will require well developed theories of this mental life expressed
in mentalistic non-neural terms. The problem then with standard practice is not
its reduction but its methodological myopia. And KGG-MMP recognizes this. The
paper ends with an appeal for a more “pluralistic” neuroscience, not an
anti-reductionist one.
Second, KGG-MMP gives a nice sketch of how WV has become so
prevalent. It provides a couple of reasons. First, has been the tremendous
success of “technique driven neuroscience” (481). There can be no doubt that
there has been an impressive improvement in the technology available to study
the brain at the neuronal level. New and better machines, new and better
computing systems, new and better maps of where things are happening. Put these
all together and it is almost irresistible to grab for the low hanging fruit
that such techniques bring into focus. Nor, indeed should this urge be
resisted. What needs resisting is the conclusion that because these sorts of
data can be productively gathered and analyzed that these data suffice to
answer the fundamental questions.
KGG-MMP traces the problem to a dictum of Monod’s: “what is
true of the bacterium is true of the elephant.” KGG-MMP claims that this has
been understood within cog-neuro as claiming that “what is true for the circuit
is true for the behavior” and thus that “molecular biology and its techniques
should serve as the model of understanding in neuroscience” (481).
This really is a pretty poor form of argument. It
effectively denies the possibility of emergence. Here’s Martin Reese (here)
making the obvious point:
Macroscopic systems that
contain huge numbers of particles manifest ‘emergent’ properties that are best
understood in terms of new, irreducible concepts appropriate to the level of
the system. Valency, gastrulation (when cells begin to differentiate in
embryonic development), imprinting, and natural selection are all examples.
Even a phenomenon as unmysterious as the flow of water in pipes or rivers is
better understood in terms of viscosity and turbulence, rather than
atom-by-atom interactions. Specialists in fluid mechanics don’t care that water
is made up of H2O molecules; they can understand how waves break
and what makes a stream turn choppy only because they envisage liquid as a
continuum.
Single molecules of H2O do not flow.
If one is interested in fluid mechanics then understanding will come only by
going beyond the level of the single molecule or atom. Similary if one is
interested in the brain mechanisms underlying cognition or behavior then it is
very likely that we will need to know a lot about how groups of fundamental
neural elements interact, not just how one does what it does. So just as a
single bird doesn’t flock, nor a single water molecule flow, nor a single
gastric cell digest, so neither does a single brain particle (e.g. neuron)
think. We will need more.
Before I get to what more, I should add here that
I don’t actually think that Mondo meant what KGG-MMP take him to have
meant. What Monod meant was that the principles of biology that one finds in
the bacterium are the same as those that we find in the elephant. There is
little reason to suppose, he suggested, that what makes elephants different
from bacteria lies in their smallest parts respecting different physical laws.
It’s not as if we expect the biochemistry to change. What KGG-MMP and Reese
observe is that this does not mean that all is explained by just understanding
how the fundamental parts work. This is correct, even if Monod’s claim is also correct.
Let me put this another way: what we want are explanations.
And explanations of macro phenomena (e.g. flight, cognition) seldom reduce to
properties of the basic parts. We can completely understand how these work
without having the slightest insight into why the macro system has the features
it does. Here is Reese again on reduction in physics:
So reductionism is true in a
sense [roughly Monod’ sense, NH]. But it’s seldom true in a useful sense.
Only about 1 per cent of scientists are particle physicists or cosmologists.
The other 99 per cent work on ‘higher’ levels of the hierarchy. They’re held up
by the complexity of their subject, not by any deficiencies in our
understanding of subnuclear physics.
So, even given the utility of understanding the
brain at the molecular level (and nobody denies that this is useful), we need
more than WV allows for. We need a way of mapping two different levels of
description onto one another. In other words, we need to solve what Embick and
Poeppel have called the “granularity mismatch problem” (see here).
And for this we need to find a way of matching up behavioral descriptions with
neural ones. And this requires “fine grained” behavioral theories that limn
mental mechanisms (“component parts and sub-routinges”) as finely as neural
accounts describe brain mechanisms. Sadly, as KGG-MMP notes, behavioral
investigation “has increasingly been marginalized or at best postponed”
(481-2), and this has made moving beyond the WV difficult. Rectifying this
requires treating behavior “as a foundational phenomenon in its own right”
(482).[3]
Here is one more quibble before going forward. I am
not really fond of the term ‘behavioral.’ What we want is a way of matching up
cognitive mechanisms with neural ones. We are not really interested in
explaining actual behavior but in explaining the causal springs and mechanisms
that produce behavior. Focusing on behavior leads to competence/performance
confusions that are always best avoided. That said, the term seems embedded in
the cog-neuro literature (no doubt a legacy of psychology’s earlier
disreputable behaviorist past) and cannot be easily dislodged. What KGG-MMP
intends is that we should look for mental
models and use these to explore neural models that realize these mental
systems. Of course, we assume that mental systems yield behaviors in specific
circumstances, but like all good scientific theories, the goal is to expose the
mental causes behind the specific behavior and it is these mental causal
factors whose brain realization we are interested in understanding. The examples KGG-MMP gives show that this is
the intended point.
Third, KGG-MMP nicely isolates why neuroscience needs mental
models. Or as KGG-MMP puts is: “Why is it the case that explanations of
experiments at the neural level are dependent on higher level vocabulary and
concepts?” Because “this dependency is intrinsic to the very concept of a
“mechanism”.” The crucial observation is that “the components of a mechanism do
different things than the mechanism organized as a whole” (485). As Marr noted,
feathers are part of the bird flight mechanism, but feathers don’t fly. To
understand how birds fly requires more than a careful description of their feathers.
So too with neurons.
Put another way, as mental life (and so behavior) is an
emergent property of neurons how
neurons subvene mental processes will not be readily apparent by only studying
neural properties singularly or collectively.
Fourth, KGG-MMP gives several nice concrete examples of
fruitful interactions between mental and neural accounts. I do not review them
here save to say that sound localization in barn owls makes its usual grand
appearance. However, KGG-MMP provides several other examples as well and it is
always useful to have a bunch of these available on hand.
Last, KGG-MMP got me thinking about how GGish work
intersects with the neuro concerns the paper raises, in particular minimalism
and its potential impact for neuroscience. I have suggested elsewhere (e.g. here)
that MP finally offers a way of bridging the granularity gap that Embick and
Poeppel. The problem as they saw it, was that the primitives GGers were
comfortable with (binding, movement, c-command) did not map well to primitives
neuro types were comfortable with. If, as KGG-MMP suggests, we take the notion
of the “circuit” as the key bridging notion, the problem with GG was that it
did not identify anything simple enough to be a plausible correlate to a neural
circuit. Another way of saying this is that theories like GB (though very
useful) did not “dissect [linguistic, NH] behavior into its component parts or
subroutines” (481). It did not carve linguistic capacity at its joints. What
minimalism offers is a way of breaking GB parts down into simpler
subcomponents. Reducing macro GB properties to products of simple operations
like Merge or Agree or Check Feature
promises to provide mental parts simple enough to be neurally interpretable. As
KGG-MMP makes clear finding the right behavioral/mental models matters and
breaking complex mental phenomena down into its simpler parts will be part of
finding the most useful models for neural realization.
Ok, that’s it. The paper is accessible and readable and
useful. Take a look.
[1]
As we all know, the meaning of the name is just what it denotes so there is no
semantic contribution that ‘wrong’ and ‘right’ make to WV and RV above.
[2]
The quotes are to signal the possibility that Gallistel is right that much
neuronal/cognitive computation takes place sub
neuronally.
[3]
Again, IMO, though I agree with the thrust of this position, it is very badly
put. It is not behavior that is foundational but mentalistic accounts of
behavior, the mechanisms that underlie it, that should be treated as
foundational. In all cases, what we are interested in are the basic mechanisms
not their products. The latter are interesting exactly to the degree that they
illuminate the basic etiology.
Google drive link didn't work for me, but this one did
ReplyDeleteThx. Fixed it. N
Delete"Focusing on behavior leads to competence/performance confusions that are always best avoided."
ReplyDeleteTo the contrary, I think the message of the Krakauer et al. piece is that looking away from behavior can lead to this kind of confusion. Performance (i.e. behavior) is one of the most important pieces of evidence we can use to infer competence and cognitive mechanisms. Reframing their 'behavioral' to 'mental' detracts from this, and 'we are not really interested in explaining actual behavior' is the reductio ad absurdum that follows from it.
Cognitive theories are not theories of behavior (unless, of course you are a behaviorist or associationist). It is a theory of mechanisms underlying the behavior. Behavior is evidence for cognitive mechanism. The circuit is where cognitive and neuronal mechanisms meet (that's the claim in the paper). Talking about behavior obscures what the cognitive side has to deliver. Of course behavior is the evidence. But a theory is not ABOUT the evidence but about the underlying causal structure. Failure to realize this will make bridging the granularity divide impossible.
DeleteLast point: nobody aims to explain "actual" behavior. The behavior that is almost always relevant is factitious; manufactured under ideal circumstances. Nor is this unique to the mental/neural sciences. This is true everywhere. Experiments are very artificial. But even these are not what are explained. Rather they are what are used to propel what does the explaining. So, it is not "actual" behavior that is the the data used nor is it the artificial data that is the target of theory. It is what is sued to construct a theory of the relevant mechanisms and these are what need reconciliation and what must be stated at the right grain size.