I am an unabashed and irritatingly vocal admirer of
Chomsky’s many intellectual contributions. I read everything he writes and has
written in Linguistics and Philosophy (ok, almost
everything: I came to linguistics from philosophy so I have refrained from dipping
into the pleasures of SPE and a few of Chomsky’s other phonologically targeted
products) and a very large chunk of his political work. So it came to me as quite a surprise to find
out about the “Chomsky Problem” in the August 29th 2012 issue of the
TLS. I have run into many “problems”
over the years: The “Maria Problem” in the Sound of Music (singing novitiates
can be bothersome), the “three body problem” (something you want to avoid if
you value simple calculations), the “Mind-Body Problem,” the “Problem of Other
Minds,” and the “Problem of Induction,” (these have occupied philosophers for a
long time and will no doubt be hot topics for a while still), Das Adam Smith
Probleme (Germans puzzle over how one guy could have written two books that
appear to be quite complementary (who can guess what puzzles German
intellectuals!), Theory of Moral
Sentiments and The Wealth of Nations)
among others. But never the “Chomsky
Problem.” David Hawkes explains it as follows: Chomsky’s writings in
theoretical linguistics and his political commentary “appear to contradict each
other.” What’s the contradiction? Hawkes believes (and he suggests that he is
not alone) that (1) and (2) cannot both be coherently entertained.
(1)
UG is a feature of human brains and is hard
wired into our genes
(2)
Conservative forms of social organization are
neither immutable nor natural
The problem seems to be that (1) “can be easily
characterized as reactionary” because it “diminishes the influence of the environment
on human behavior,” which apparently implies that that those forms of social
organization that do exist must exist as a matter of biology. It doesn’t take a
lot of effort to see that whatever the relation between (1) and (2) might be,
“contradiction” is not one of them. The truth of (1) has no implications whatsoever
regarding that of (2), a position that Chomsky adopts, as Hawkes observes.
Independent of (1)’s relation to (2), Hawkes’ claims
concerning (1) are very confused. He
seems to identify genetic coding with immutability and immunity from
environmental influence (viz. puberty is genetically programmed but
environmental factors can accelerate or delay its onset) . However, very few
genetically determined characteristics are so isolated from all environmental
impact (think diet and height). Certainly, as far as language goes, even if UG
is genetically coded, which particular language a speaker acquires is acutely sensitive
to her linguistic environment. There is no plausible logical route from the
fact that all languages have certain formal structural similarities to the
conclusion that they are all identical in every particular, or, even more of a
stretch, that because all languages
have a common form, anything at all follows about social organization. Indeed,
even if every particular about a given language was coded in the genes (a
position that nobody entertains), it is hard to see what this would imply for
the large social and political concerns Hawkes is worried about. After all,
face recognition and pitch perception have genetic components but neither
Hawkes nor anyone else has suggested that this has any political implications.
I conclude that Hawkes cannot literally mean what he says.
Rather, Hawkes is tempting us with the following slippery slope inference: If
any feature of human behavior has an “immutable” biological basis, every one
does. As Hawkes sees it there is an
“affinity” which inclines those that adopt (1) to embrace conservative forms of
political and social organization. Is there any truth to this?
Not on the face of it. As he notes, Chomsky himself rejects
any connection. But let’s for a moment
take the supposition seriously, for there is something decidedly odd about
Hawkes’ views for they seem to assume that non-conservative forms of social
organization require that we assume that human nature has no genetic
roots. And this is very
problematic. Why so?
First, it is unlikely to be true. Daily, we find evidence that many of our
cognitive and affective characteristics are elaborated on biologically given
foundations. It’s a bad idea to tie
opposition to oppressive forms of social and political organization on the
extreme view that biology has nothing to do with human nature.
Second, it is unnecessary to take such an extreme position.
Imagine (as some have proposed) that humans come equipped with a kind of UG for
ethics and morality (Rawls, Kant) or have a natural communal instinct
(Aristotle, Bukharin) or a built in capacity for sympathy (Hutchinson). On this
view, some forms of moral judgment are more “natural” than others, at least for
humans. What follows from this? As regards what we ought to do, not much, if one distinguishes (as I do, at least for
rough and ready purposes) what is the case from what should be the case, i.e.
facts from values. At most what these kinds of considerations talk to is the feasibility of one or another form of
social organization given the human propensities on which they can be founded.
For example, social fraternity (we are all in this together) can live on the
natural sociability of humans and the sympathy the feel for one another’s
circumstances. Similarly the concern for justice can exploit our sense of
sympathy (Hume) or our common faculty of reason (Kant).
Third, nothing
(absolutely nothing) that we know from
biology, psychology or neuroscience precludes any of the forms of social
organization that Hawkes or Chomsky or me cares about. This does not mean to
say that there don’t exist good reasons for preferring some social arrangements
to others. Rather, the relevant reasons for one preference or another have
little to do with discoveries in biology, psychology or neuroscience. The fact
is that one can learn more about human nature that is polictically or socially
relevant from a good novel (or even a bad one) than from the “deep” insights
science has provided (hint: one should always treat NYT headlines in the Tuesday
science section with considerable skepticism). No doubt many bad arguments have been provided to
buttress one or another execrable policy (think back to the IQ debates of yore
or the speculations concerning the genetic inability of females to do math).
But bad arguments of this kind are not bad because they are based in biology,
they are bad because they are bad science, bad philosophy and bad public policy
and should be opposed as such.
Fourth, the anything-can-be-human-nature view is also
susceptible to abuse. After all if human
nature is so malleable that it can tolerate any
form of social and political organization why prefer one to another? Skinner, a very pure environmentalist, argued in Beyond
Freedom and Dignity that freedom and dignity were illusions that stood in
the way of a utopia based on behavior modification implemented by wise
psychologist kings. There is more than enough fodder here to argue that extreme
environmentalism has nasty consequences for democracy. Or, put positively, the
belief that humans as such share
certain basic cognitive and affective features (i.e. share them just in virtue
of being humans) can ground (and has grounded) ideals of equality, freedom and justice
with important social and political implications for how societies ought to be
organized. An old enlightenment theme that keeps cropping up in Chomsky’s political
writings concerns each human’s creative potential (think Kant, Rousseau, von
Humboldt), an everyday manifestation of which is the creative use of language. Thinking
of people in this way suggests forms of social organization where this creative
potential is not stifled and is allowed to flower. This doesn’t follow logically, but as Hawkes
might say, there is an affinity here. An
old prof of mine, Harry Bracken, once pointed out that rationalist conceptions
of human nature provide “mild conceptual brakes” against invidiously
distinguishing among humans (aka: racism) and provide a basis for treating all equitably and
with common respect. As Bracken noted,
this is not an apodictic truth, but such conceptions of human nature might provide a slight nudge in a decent
direction.
So, contra Hawkes, Chomsky is certainly right that nativist
conceptions of language are logically independent of questions of social and political organization. Indeed, science
has yet to uncover a conception of human nature capable of having any
interesting moral or political consequences, nor do I believe that such
discoveries are on the horizon. In sum, right now the general form of the “Chomsky Problem” (what
does science tell us about how to organize society) is not worth answering for it rests on the faulty presupposition that science has something interesting and original to add to the conversation. Science cannot tell us that we ought to treat one another decently, and
anyone who needs science to “confirm” this moral precept won’t believe the
evidence anyway.
Hawkes is notorious for his purposefully (and unnecessarily) inflammatory writing (at least, this is what my fellow students who study literature under him tell me). I'd love to have written a rebuttal (or even better, a piece on Hawkes's favorite author John Milton without having any idea what I'm talking about!), but you've done quite nicely! Great to see you invoke Harry too, he and Chomsky are among the only defenses we ASU students have against the constant assault of empiricism. Much respect!
ReplyDelete